Right to White: Combating Colorblindness Through Monochromatic Dreams - Zachary Davis
Prelude:
I remember in my
intro to philosophy class the Professor taught Hume’s Problem of Induction. They
repeatedly corrected a popularized misinterpretation of the argument: inductive
reasoning employed in science can never prove a 100% causal link, and can only
prove strong correlational evidence that imply usually X corresponds with Y. Rather
the devastating implication of Hume’s problem of induction is that past evidence
has no bearing whatsoever on future occurrences, there is no reason to believe
that gravitational forces will operate the same tomorrow as today. In other
words causation is not just to 100% prove, but there is no reason correlational
evidence has any effect on the strength of a causal link.
The reason I
recall this example, is because I’ve observed a similar gap in understanding
accounts of structural discrimination particularly accounts like Harris which criticize
neutrality and colorblindness. Like the scientist, people are incredibly
willing to accept they are not perfect neutral agents, and cannot 100% control
or combat their implicit biases. Yet in doing so they not only forfeit the
responsibility to take corrective actions, but additionally maintain the goal
of neutrality. Rather, there is no evidence moves towards more neutrality
decrease colorblindness or discrimination. The problem is not just with colorblindness
in our current society, but colorblindness in the ideal society, which
continually builds biases back in through incoherent commitments to equality.
To give a material
example of these commitments’ problems, in Prof. Shankar’s work “Nothing Sells
like Whiteness” they discuss marketing campaigns targeted at racial minorities
move from a focus on Multiculturalism, with agencies primarily staffed by peoples
of individual communities using particular cultural messaging towards specific
cultural groups i.e. Latino, Black, Chinese etc., to a move to diversity advertising
in the 90s, which has uses messaging about diversity and equality generally.
These ads typically are handled by more mainstream advertising agencies, have
scripting targeting the majority/white audience, and feature a variety of racially
cast actors typically including a white representative. The white representative
is sometimes used as the ‘main character’/viewer insert in interacting with
racial minorities, or otherwise representing the good.
Main Paper:
I was going to
write the main body of my blog post on expanding my previous argument of
Beauvoir through a combination with my new familiarity with Hegel and Race and
Gender theory, to extend Harris’ discussion of what it means to be recognized
as white. However, I’ve written on similar things in the past, and will in the
future, so I think its more interesting for now to just pose these as questions
for my cohort:
What does it mean
to be recognized as white?
What does it mean
to be white?
Do you have a right
(property right potentially?) to your racial identification? And to what extent
is race decided externally/internally? i.e. the racial identity of the person
who grew up with two black parents who pass as black, but due to a skin
condition, passes as white.
Is recognition beneficial
in combating discrimination?
How is recognition
power controlled/monitored? How should it be controlled/monitored if at all?
Previous paper written on the exact same reading last semester for Phil of Law if anyone wants to read it.
Disclaimer: Some of my opinions have evolved, and much of it was already meant
to be thought provoking especially the passing section which I think I
personally disagreed with when written, but I think anti-recognition/unintelligibility
movements are given way less thought then deserved:
Stealing Whiteness as Property: A Deep Dive into Identity
Relationships
In
this paper, I make two main arguments. First, Harris’s account of whiteness as
property is better understand as an issue founded in identity relationships and
fundamentally ensured by liberalism and theories of equality. In doing so I
look to both Frank Wilderson’s afro-pessimism and applications of Beauvoir to
race for explaining this identity relationships. Therefore, Harris’ attempts at
policy and ideological change through affirmative action will result in a new
stage of preservation through transformation as theories of equality move to
new privileges whiteness has property over. Second, through exploring stealing
whiteness as property I’ll attempt to show solutions are possible but must
operate unilaterally at the identity level sans liberalism.
Wilderson uses Harris’ examples of
preservation through transformation between Chattel Slavery, Jim Crow Laws, and
the Prison Industrial Complex as foundational evidence for the failure of liberalism
frameworks. For wilderson, societal progress for blackness is impossible as
they are situated as the other, and forcibly alienated from their selves. Applying
Harris, whiteness as property can be understood as having property over the
solution, and the security which comes from that assurance. The modern white
progressive may feel shame in their unique access to whiteness, and thus via
liberalism desire to distribute that whiteness through methods such as
affirmative action. In doing so, via whiteness they access the security of
having a solution. With every transformed racial system there was an end goal
determined by whiteness: slavery abolition became acceptable with the coming of
Jim Crow, desegregation with the prison industrial complex, and whatever will come
from prison reforms or abolition. Blackness is forced into an unending pursuit
of that solution always situated in the future as racial equality resulting in
cruel optomism. Therefore, from an afro-pessimist framework Harris’ own
arguments understood through this relationship between whiteness and blackness
lead to pessimistic conclusions about liberalism and Harris’ solutions.
Beauvoir
understands a distinction between identities as nature i.e. sex and identities
socially constructed i.e. gender, or being as race vs becoming race. Phrases
such as “You are as eloquent as a white person,” display this divide, where
eloquent black people are seen as becoming white when adopting white properties
or how women “fail as women,” when they adopt masculine qualities. For Beauvoir
this shifting social identity is fundamentally constructed in the comparison
between what people are seen as being, and the properties they are seen as
becoming. Therefore, in the social relation there is a fundamental otherness or
negativity in relation to whiteness constitutive to the social categories,
black traits are not-white traits, i.e. if eloquence is constitutive to
whiteness then the lack of such is found in the negation of blackness.
Therefore, subordination is fundamentally constitutive to the relationship, to
be a master is to be white, and to be a slave is to be black. Harris’ account
of property exists as an expression of that relationship, or the extent of
ownership over whiteness and therefore valuable characteristics. Once more
liberalism appears incoherent as a solution, insofar as affirmative action
fundamentally values black assimilation to whiteness via adoption of white
qualities i.e. high SAT scores on white culture written by white judges etc.
Rather
I find in what Harris and liberalism reject – stealing property through passing
a valuable solution. Passing allows a person to steal ownership over whiteness,
rather then being recognized as being black while becoming white, they are
presumed being white while becoming black through performing the deceptive act
for their own motives. Moreover, passing undermines belief in the ownership of
whiteness. Unlike white people, white-passing persons do not understand
whiteness as intrinsic to their own identities. As such, they uniquely hold the
freedom of how they choose to present whiteness through passing. I.e. they may
represent whiteness as deferring to black people on issues of racial
inequality. Even the white ally cannot mirror this, because their self is in
part beholden to societal standards of whiteness. Changing what society
understands whiteness as while subscribing in their whiteness relative to those
standards, requires a change in belief as to what they are. Therefore stealing
ownership over whiteness has the sole potential to avoid the recreation through
white liberalism of whiteness-owned solutions which reify racial
discrimination.
I completely agree with the point about how when people accept they can not be perfectly neutral, they end up forfeiting their responsibilities. The examples given showing the commitment problems in marketing campaigns also reminded me of the lack of representation in the media as a whole and the tendency for people to write in stereotypes which subconsciously influence the way people think and view one another.
ReplyDeleteOne thing I did not completely grasp was how stealing property or anti-recognition through passing could be a valuable solution/what problems it would ultimately solve (if the goal is to dismantle whiteness as property.) Although white-passing people have the option of choosing how they present their identities, I believe that doing so only perpetuates the concept of whiteness being advantageous. Not all people are able to pass as white, and the people who do are reiterating the idea that being white equates to having a better position in society.